96 Cummings Point Road
Stamford, Connecticut 06902
U.S.A.
Company Perspectives:
The Aristotle Corporation, founded in 1986 and headquartered in New Haven, Connecticut, is a leading manufacturer and global distributor of education, health, and agricultural products.
History of The Aristotle Corporation
Originally formed as a bank holding company, The Aristotle Corporation is now involved in the manufacturing and distribution of a variety of education, health, and agricultural products through two primary subsidiaries: Nasco International, Inc. and Simuladids, Inc. Their products, mostly sold through catalogs, are divided between educational offerings and commercial offerings. Educational offerings include arts and crafts items for schoolchildren; classroom science equipment, as well as live and preserved specimens; math teaching aids for schoolchildren; healthcare training materials (such as manikins used for training in cardiopulmonary resuscitation) appropriate for nursing and medical school, emergency training professionals, and health teachers; teaching aids for family and consumer sciences, targeting dieticians, nutrition instructors, and family and consumer science teachers; fun learning activities for preschool children; and items for use by physical education professionals. Aristotle's commercial offerings include teaching aids for agricultural education to help farmers and ranchers with such tasks as breed identification, grooming, artificial insemination, and animal health; products for activity therapists in nursing homes and assisted living homes, including arts and crafts and games; resources that help in conducting an activity program in an assisted living home; and Whirl Pak sampling bags for use by food and microbiology laboratories. With its headquarters located in Stamford, Connecticut, Aristotle maintains operations in California, Colorado, Michigan, New York, and Ontario, Canada. Although publicly traded on the NASDAQ, the company is 90 percent owned by Geneve Corporation, which is run by Aristotle's president Steven B. Lapin and board member Edward Netter.
Bank Holding Company Formed in 1986
The roots of Aristotle date back to 1986 when FFB Corporation was established as a holding company for New Haven-based First Federal Bank of Connecticut as part of an effort to take the federal thrift public. In 1988, the bank changed from a federal charter to a state chartered savings bank, in the process changing its name to First Constitution Bank. In turn, FFB Corporation changed its name to First Constitution Financial Corporation. At the time of the switch, the bank had assets of $1.8 billion, but some poor real estate investments in Connecticut soon put the institution in severe financial jeopardy when the bottom fell out of the local real estate market. Displeased shareholders, including Geneve Corp., forced the resignation of the chief executive officer of the bank and the holding company by threatening a proxy fight. The board was also enlarged to accommodate a director committed to the protection of shareholder interests. As loses mounted--during the first months of 1990 First Constitution lost $58.4 million--the bank was forced to cut staff and close three branch offices. The downward spiral continued over the next two years and in October 1992, when First Constitution was unable to complete a recapitalization plan it had filed with regulators, the Federal Deposit Insurance Corp. took preemptive action. Even before the bank was technically insolvent, it seized control and sold the bank to Webster Financial Corp., another Connecticut bank holding company.
First Constitution Financial Corporation wrote off its investment in the bank to the sum of $25.4 million. What was left was a corporate shell with no operating subsidiaries. Nevertheless, it did have $10 million in cash plus $120 million in tax credits. These tax credits, however, could not be used unless the company was actually engaged in a business. In April 1993, First Constitution changed its name to The Aristotle Corporation, and in September, nearly a year since the FDIC seizure, the holding company returned to active business, paying $4.5 million to acquire Strouse, Adler Company. 132-year-old Strouse designed, manufactured, and marketed women's intimate apparel in two categories: specialty brassieres and women's shapewear. Specialty brassieres were used with backless, strapless, and halter-top garments. The company's shapewear products provided abdominal support and control, much like a traditional girdle. Items included "body briefers," medium control panties, and control bottoms. Core Strouse brand names were Smoothie and Fleur de Lace. Customers included such major department stores as Macy's, Bloomingdale's, Nordstrom, Nieman Marcus, and Lord & Taylor. The company also marketed its wares through catalogs and provided private label goods to retailers, including Victoria's Secret, Dillard's, and JC Penney.
FDIC Suit Resolved in 1995
Aristotle was still not free of its previous banking experience, however. In April 1995, the FDIC sued the company in an effort to recover tax refunds paid and due to Aristotle. A class action lawsuit filed in 1990 also remained pending. Finally, in 1996 Aristotle was able to put these outstanding matters to rest. It signed a settlement agreement with the FDIC that allowed the company to retain $2 million of a $4 million tax refund; on its side, Aristotle agreed to relinquish further claims to another $1.7 million in tax refunds. In return, Aristotle and its former officers and directors, including those with First Constitution Bank, were absolved from any further claims connected to the 1992 failure of the bank. Furthermore, in August 1996, Aristotle reached a settlement on the 1990 class action suit when a Federal Court Judge approved a proposal. According to the company, the settlement presented no material financial impact on Aristotle. However, with the cloud of litigation removed, Aristotle had a chance to truly move beyond its banking roots, raise new capital, and concentrate on the task of growing shareholder value.
Although there were indications at the time of the Strouse acquisition that Aristotle might make further acquisitions in the apparel industry, management was disappointed with the performance of its lone subsidiary. In July 1998, Aristotle sold Strouse to Sara Lee Corporation for $21.5 million in cash plus the assumption of $8 million in debt. As a result, once again Aristotle was without an operating subsidiary. Nearly a year would pass before Aristotle settled on a new line of business: the fast growing for-profit education field. In April 1999, it acquired Woodstock, New York-based Simulaids, Inc. for approximately $8.7 million. Established in 1963, Simulaids manufactured health and medical education teaching aids. Products included manikins and simulation kits for training in CPR, emergency rescue, and patient care. Simulaid sold its products internationally through distributors and catalogs. Primary end-users included nursing and medical schools as well as fire and emergency medical departments. In connection with the Simulaids acquisition, Aristotle established a relationship with Nasco International, Inc., a major manufacturer and distributor of educational materials which agreed to help Aristotle in adding more assets in the for-profit education field. Nasco was a unit of Aristotle's major shareholder, Geneve Corporation.
Aristotle's next move in the education field came the following year, in September 2000, when it bought an 80 percent stake in Safe Passage International, Inc. for an aggregate price of some $1.6 million. Management of Safe Passage retained the remaining 20 percent of the business. Operating out of Rochester, New York, Safe Passage was started in 1989 to develop computer-based training programs in conjunction with the airline industry and the Federal Aviation Agency for use in airport security. Aristotle hoped to create synergies between its two subsidiaries with the goal of transforming traditional medical manikins into computer-driven patient simulators. Moreover, Aristotle was interested in developing computer-based training programs that could provide online continuing education credits for healthcare professionals.
Aristotle soon veered away from the high-tech arena. In November 2001, majority shareholder Geneve engineered a reverse merger between Aristotle and Wisconsin-based Nasco, with Aristotle the surviving entity. Nasco was far larger than Aristotle, generating more than $150 million in annual revenues in fiscal 2001 compared to the $8.1 million posted by the combined efforts of Simulaids and Safe Passage. However, Aristotle still retained significant tax credits from its previous life as First Constitution Financial Corporation. By being folded into Aristotle, Nasco was able to enjoy a tremendous tax break, to the benefit of both Aristotle and Nasco shareholders. As a result of the merger, completed in 2002, Geneve increased its stake in Aristotle from 51 percent to more than 90 percent. While Aristotle's chief executive stayed on in that capacity, Geneve's president and chief operating officer, Steven B. Lapin, assumed these same positions in the much larger Aristotle Corporation.
Nasco was launched in 1940 by a Wisconsin agriculture teacher who, working out of his basement, created instructional books and assorted teaching aids. Over the next 60 years, the company branched off in numerous directions, ultimately selling more than 50,000 products through 25 specialty catalogs aimed at teachers, farmers, and industrialists. Nasco sold fake substances such as blubber, yogurt, crackers, and wheat bread. It also sold very real African clawed frogs, used by researchers around the world and raised in the company's own colonies as part of Nasco's lab supplies and kits sold to schools. Other educational products included a crying infant simulator and a realistic human head and torso dummy used to practice dislodging food and clearing blocked airways. Nevertheless, only three of the company's 25 catalogs served the healthcare market; the bulk of Nasco's business was devoted to the marketing of educational supplies for K-12 schoolchildren. The addition of Simulaids' proprietary mannequins and simulation kits were expected to greatly enhance Nasco's three healthcare catalogs. The combined business also hoped to use its greater breadth in Nasco's planned effort to expand into the Canadian healthcare business.
Safe Passage Interest Sold in 2002
In 2002, Aristotle made a pair of changes. In September, CEO John Crawford announced his retirement. Although he stayed on as a member of the board and the executive committee, responsibility for the day-to-day running of the business became the province of president and COO Lapin. In addition, Aristotle chief financial officer resigned, replaced by Dean Johnson, Nasco's CFO for the previous five years. Also in 2002, near the end of the year, Aristotle sold its 80 percent interest in Safe Passage, thus ending the company's foray into computer-driven educational products. Financially, the reverse merge between Aristotle and Nasco showed immediate results in fiscal 2002. While the two business had combined for $162 million in revenues for fiscal 2001, and income showed only modest growth in fiscal 2002, to $165.9, the impact on the bottom line of the balance sheet was hard to ignore. Net earnings increased from $8.8 million in fiscal 2001 to $30.3 million in fiscal 2002.
Aristotle continued to grow its for-profit educational business in 2003. It acquired Hann Crafts, an Otterbein, Indiana, company that produced and sold sewing kits used in middle-school family and consumer science classes. In order to fund further acquisitions to strengthen Aristotle's holdings, management announced in October 2003 that it had signed a five-year, $45 million credit agreement with Bank One, N.A. and Johnson Bank of Wisconsin. This revolving line of credit was a significant improvement over the company's prior $31 million credit capacity. Aristotle experienced a decline in revenues during fiscal 2003, to $163.2 million, but earnings before income taxes improved from $16.7 million in 2002 to $20.3 million in 2003. Business conditions were generally poor for the company, in large part due to many troubled state economies, which adversely impacted school budgets around the country and resulted in decreased sales for Aristotle. Nevertheless, the company, after making the transition from bank holding company to a for-profit educational concern, appeared well positioned to enjoy ongoing growth in the next phase of its corporate history.
Principal Subsidiaries: Simulaids, Inc.; Haan Crafts Corporation.
Principal Competitors: United Industrial Corporation; Vital Signs, Inc.
Related information about Aristotle
Greek philosopher, scientist, and physician, one of the greatest
figures in the history of Western thought, born in Stagira,
Macedonia. In 367 he went to Athens, where he was associated with
Plato's Academy until Plato's death in 347 BC. He then spent time in Asia Minor and in Mytilene
(on Lesbos). In 342 BC he was invited by
Philip of Macedon to educate his son, Alexander (later, the Great).
He returned to Athens (335 BC) and
opened a school (the Lyceum); his followers were called
Peripatetics, supposedly from his practice of walking up and
down restlessly during his lectures. After Alexander's death (323
BC), there was strong anti-Macedonian
sentiment in Athens; Aristotle was accused of impiety and, perhaps
with Socrates' fate in mind, escaped to Chalcis in Euboea, where he
died the next year.
Aristotle's writings represented an enormous, encyclopedic
output over virtually every field of knowledge: logic, metaphysics,
ethics, politics, rhetoric, poetry, biology, zoology, physics, and
psychology. The bulk of the work that survives actually consists of
unpublished material in the form of lecture notes or students'
textbooks; but even this incomplete corpus is extraordinary for its
range, originality, systematization, and sophistication, and his
work exerted an enormous influence on mediaeval philosophy
(especially through St Thomas Aquinas), Islamic philosophy
(especially through Averroës), and indeed on the whole Western
intellectual and scientific tradition. The works most read today
include the Metaphysics (the book written ‘after the
Physics’), Nicomachean Ethics, Politics,
Poetics, De anima, and the Organon (treatises
on logic).
era = Ancient
philosophy
| birth = 384 BC
| death = March 7
322 BC
| school_tradition = Gave rise to Aristotelianism and the Peripatetic school
| main_interests = Ethics, Politics, Metaphysics, Science, Logic
| influences = Plato
| influenced = Almost all of western philosophy and science afterward
| notable_ideas = The Golden mean, Reason, Passion
}}
Aristotle (Greek: , Aristotél?s) (384 BC ? March 7, 322
BC) was an ancient Greek philosopher, a student of Plato and teacher of Alexander the Great.
He wrote books on diverse subjects, including physics, poetry, zoology, logic, rhetoric, politics, government, and biology, none of which survive in their entirety.
Aristotle, along with Plato and Socrates, is generally considered one of the most
influential of ancient Greek philosophers. They transformed Presocratic Greek philosophy into
the foundations of Western philosophy as we know it. The writings of Plato
and Aristotle founded two of the most important schools of Ancient
philosophy.
Although Aristotle wrote dialogues early in his career, no more
than fragments of these have survived. The works of Aristotle that
exist today are in treatise form and were, for the most part, unpublished
texts. Among the most important are Physics,
Metaphysics (or Ontology), Nicomachean Ethics, Politics,
De Anima (On the
Soul) and Poetics.
Aristotle is known for being one of the few figures in history who
studied almost every subject possible at the time, probably being
one of the first polymaths. In science, Aristotle studied anatomy, astronomy, economics, embryology, geography, geology, meteorology, physics, and zoology. In philosophy,
Aristotle wrote on aesthetics, ethics, government, metaphysics, politics, psychology, rhetoric and theology. He also dealt with education, foreign customs, literature and poetry. His combined works
practically constitute an encyclopedia of Greek knowledge.
Biography
Early life and studies at the Academy
Aristotle was born in a colony of Andros on the Macedonian peninsula of Chalcidice in 384 BC. His father, who is named
Nicomachus, was court physician to King Amyntas III of
Macedon. It is known that she died early in Aristotle's
life.
When Nicomachus also died, in Aristotle's tenth year, he was left
an orphan and placed
under the guardianship of his uncle, Proxenus of
Atarneus.
He taught Aristotle Greek, rhetoric, and poetry (O'Connor et al., 2004). Aristotle also
attend Plato's school for young Greek aristocracy, it is a well
known fact that Aristotle was Plato's favourite student. when he
went to Athens at the age
of 18, he was likely already trained in the investigation of
natural phenomena.
From the age of 18 to 37 Aristotle remained in Athens as a pupil of
Plato and distinguished
himself at the Academy. The relations between Plato and Aristotle
have formed the subject of various legends, many of which depict
Aristotle unfavourably. In fact, Aristotle's conduct after the
death of Plato, his continued association with Xenocrates and other Platonists, and his allusions
in his writings to Plato's doctrines prove that while there were
conflicts of opinion between Plato and Aristotle, there was no lack
of cordial appreciation or mutual forbearance. Besides this, the
legends that reflect Aristotle unfavourably are allegedly traceable
to the Epicureans,
although some doubt remains of this charge. If such legends were
circulated widely by patristic writers such as Justin Martyr and Gregory Nazianzen, the
reason lies in the exaggerated esteem Aristotle was held in by the
early Christian
heretics. Aristotle then
went with Xenocrates to the court of Hermias, ruler of Atarneus in Asia Minor, married his niece, Pythias, and with her had
a daughter named Pythias after her mother. In 344 BC, Hermias was
murdered in a rebellion, and
Aristotle went with his family to Mytilene. It is also reported that he stopped on
Lesbos and briefly
conducted biological research. Then, one or two years later, he was
summoned to Pella, the Macedonian capital, by King Philip II of
Macedon to become the tutor of Alexander the Great,
who was then 13.
Plutarch wrote that
Aristotle not only imparted to Alexander a knowledge of ethics and
politics, but also of the most profound secrets of philosophy. We
have much proof that Alexander profited by contact with the
philosopher, and that Aristotle made prudent and beneficial use of
his influence over the young prince (although Bertrand Russell
disputes this). Due to this influence, Alexander provided Aristotle
with ample means for the acquisition of books and the pursuit of
his scientific investigation.
It is possible that Aristotle also participated in the education of
Alexander's boyhood friends, which may have included for example
Hephaestion and
Harpalus. Aristotle
maintained a long correspondence with Hephaestion, eventually
collected into a book, unfortunately now lost.
According to sources such as Plutarch and Diogenes, Philip had
Aristotle's hometown of Stageira burned during the 340s BC, and Aristotle
successfully requested that Alexander rebuild it. He may, as
Aulus Gellius
says, have conducted a school of rhetoric during his former residence in Athens; but now,
following Plato's example, he gave regular instruction in
philosophy in a gymnasium dedicated to Apollo Lyceios, from
which his school has come to be known as the Lyceum. (It was also called the
Peripatetic School
because Aristotle preferred to discuss problems of philosophy with
his pupils while walking around -- peripateo -- the shaded
walks -- peripatoi -- around the gymnasium).
During the thirteen years (335 BC–322 BC) which he spent as teacher
of the Lyceum, Aristotle composed most of his writings. He also
composed the several treatises (which will be mentioned below) on
physics, metaphysics, and so forth, in which the exposition is more
didactic and the
language more technical than in the Dialogues. Pliny the Elder claimed
that Alexander placed under Aristotle's orders all the hunters,
fishermen, and fowlers of the royal kingdom and all the overseers
of the royal forests, lakes, ponds and cattle-ranges, and
Aristotle's works on zoology make this statement more believable.
Aristotle was fully informed about the doctrines of his
predecessors, and Strabo
asserted that he was the first to accumulate a great library.
During the last years of Aristotle's life the relations between him
and Alexander became very strained, owing to the disgrace and
punishment of Callisthenes, whom Aristotle had recommended to
Alexander. Consequently, when Alexander's death became known in
Athens, and the outbreak occurred which led to the Lamian war, Aristotle shared
in the general unpopularity of the Macedonians. The charge of
impiety, which had been
brought against Anaxagoras and Socrates, was now brought against Aristotle. He took up
residence at his country house at Chalcis, in Euboea, and there he died the following year, 322 BC.
The story that his death was due to hemlock poisoning, as well as the legend that he threw
himself into the sea "because he could not explain the tides," are without historical
foundation.
Aristotle's legacy also had a profound influence on Islamic thought
and philosophy during the Middle Ages. Muslim thinkers such as Avicenna, .
Methodology
Aristotle defines his philosophy in terms of essence, saying that philosophy
is "the science of the universal essence of that which is actual". Plato had defined it as
the "science of the idea",
meaning by idea what we should call the unconditional basis of
phenomena. Both pupil
and master regard philosophy as concerned with the universal;
Aristotle, however, finds the universal in particular things, and called
it the essence of things, while Plato finds that the universal
exists apart from particular things, and is related to them as
their prototype or
exemplar. For
Aristotle, therefore, philosophic method implies the ascent from
the study of particular phenomena to the knowledge of essences,
while for Plato philosophic method means the descent from a
knowledge of universal ideas to a contemplation of particular
imitations of those ideas. In a certain sense, Aristotle's method
is both inductive and deductive, while Plato's is essentially deductive
from a priori
principles.
In Aristotle's terminology, the term natural philosophy
corresponds to the phenomena of the natural world, which include:
motion,
light, and the laws of physics. Many
centuries later these subjects would become the basis of modern
science, as studied through the scientific method. In contrast, in Aristotle's
time and use philosophy was taken to encompass all facets of
intellectual inquiry.
In the larger sense of the word, he makes philosophy coextensive
with reasoning, which
he also called "science". while by theoretical philosophy he means
physics, mathematics, and metaphysics.
The last, philosophy in the stricter sense, he defines as "the
knowledge of immaterial being", and calls it "first philosophy", "the
theologic science" or of "being in the highest degree of
abstraction". If logic, or, as Aristotle calls it, Analytic, be regarded as a
study preliminary to philosophy, we have as divisions of
Aristotelian philosophy (1) Logic; (2) Theoretical Philosophy, including Metaphysics, Physics, Mathematics, (3) Practical
Philosophy;
Aristotle's epistemology
Logic
Aristotle's conception of logic was the dominant form of logic up
until the advances in mathematical logic in the 19th century. However, Plato
reports that syntax was
thought of before him, by Prodikos of Keos, who was concerned by the right use of
words. Logic seems to have emerged from dialectics; Although he had
the idea of constructing a system for deduction, he was never able to construct one.
Instead, he relied on his dialectic, which was a confusion between different
sciences and methods (Boche?ski, 1951). Plato thought that
deduction would simply follow from premises, so he focused on having good premises so that
the conclusion would
follow. The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into six books
in about the early 1st century CE:
-
Categories
-
On Interpretation
-
Prior Analytics
-
Posterior Analytics
-
Topics
-
On Sophistical Refutations
The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are
composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis
of Aristotle's writings. There is one volume of Aristotle's
concerning logic not found in the Organon, namely the fourth
book of Metaphysics. (Boche?ski, 1951).
Modal logic
Aristotle is also the creator of syllogisms with modalities (modal logic). The word modal
refers to the word 'modes', explaining the fact that modal logic
deals with the modes of truth. By the modern definition of the term,
Aristotelian philosophy was not science, as this worldview did not attempt to
probe how the world actually worked through experiment. Had he only made
some observations, he would have discovered that this claim is
false.
Rather, based on what one's senses told one, Aristotelian
philosophy then depended upon the assumption that man's mind could
elucidate all the laws of the universe, based on simple observation
(without experimentation) through reason alone.
One of the reasons for this was that Aristotle held that physics
was about changing objects with a reality of their own, whereas
mathematics was about unchanging objects without a reality of their
own. This is known as the scientific method.
Although Aristotle should be credited for an important step in the
history of scientific method by founding logic as a formal science,
he posited a flawed cosmology that we may discern in selections of
the Metaphysics. From the 3rd century to the 1500s, the
dominant view held that the Earth was the centre of the universe:
at this late date it is uncontroversial that the Earth is not even
the centre of our own solar system.
Later on, Galileo proved Aristotle's theory that the heavier object
falls faster than a lighter object incorrect.
Aristotle's metaphysics
Causality
In Metaphysics
and Posterior
Assilistics, Aristotle argued that all causes of things are
beginnings; As a consequence, the major kinds of causes come under
the following divisions:
The Material
Cause is that from which a thing comes into existence as from
its parts, constituents, substratum or materials. This reduces the
explanation of causes to the parts (factors, elements,
constituents, ingredients) forming the whole (system, structure,
compound, complex, composite, or combination) (the part-whole
causation).
The Formal Cause
tells us what a thing is, that any thing is determined by the
definition, form, pattern, essence, whole, synthesis, or archetype.
It embraces the account of causes in terms of fundamental
principles or general laws, as the whole (macrostructure) is the
cause of its parts (the whole-part causation).
The Efficient
Cause is that from which the change or the ending of the change
first starts. Representing the current understanding of causality
as the relation of cause and effect, this covers the modern
definitions of "cause" as either the agent or agency or particular
events or states of affairs.
The Final Cause is
that for the sake of which a thing exists or is done, including
both purposeful and instrumental actions and activities. Also,
Aristotle indicated that the same thing can be the cause of
contrary effects, its presence and absence may result in different
outcomes.
Aristotle marked two modes of causation: proper (prior) causation
and accidental (chance) causation. Essentially, causality does not
suggest a temporal relation between the cause and the effect.
All further investigations of causality will be consisting in
imposing the favorite hierarchies on the order causes, like as
final > efficient> material > formal (Thomas Aquinas), or in
restricting all causality to the material and efficient causes or
to the efficient causality (deterministic or chance) or just to
regular sequences and correlations of natural phenomena (the
natural sciences describing how things happen instead of explaining
the whys and wherefores).
Substance, Potentiality and Actuality
Aristotle examines the concept of substance (ousia) in his Metaphysics, Book VII and he
concludes that a particular substance is a combination of
both matter and form. As he proceeds to the book
VIII, he concludes that the matter of the substance is the substratum or the stuff of
which is composed e.g. or any other differentia. The formula that gives the components
is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the
differentia is the account of the form (Metaphysics VIII, 1043a
10-30).
With regard to the change (kinesis) and its causes now, as
he defines in his Physics and On Generation
and Corruption 319b-320a, he distinguishes the coming to be
from 1. In that particular change he introduces the concept of
potentiality
(dynamis) and actuality (entelecheia) in association with the
matter and the form.
Referring to potentiality, is what a thing is capable of doing, or
being acted upon, if it is not prevented from something else.
Referring now to actuality, this is the fulfillment of the end of
the potentiality. The Formal Cause (aitia) then of that change from
potential to actual house, is the reason (logos) of the house builder and the
Final Cause is the
end, namely the house itself.
With this definition
of the particular
substance (matter and form) Aristotle tries to solve the
problem of the unity of the beings; Since, according to Plato there are two Ideas: animal
and biped, how then is man a unity? The heavenly element has
perpetual circular motion.
Aristotle's ethics
Although Aristotle wrote several works on ethics, the major one was the Nicomachean
Ethics, which is considered one of Aristotle's greatest
works; it discusses virtues. The ten books which comprise it are based on
notes from his lectures at the Lyceum and were either edited by or dedicated to
Aristotle's son, Nicomachus.
Aristotle believed that ethical knowledge is not certain
knowledge, like metaphysics and epistemology, but general knowledge. Also, as it
is a practical discipline rather than a theoretical one; Depending on how well they did
this, Aristotle said people belonged to one of four categories: the
Virtuous, the Continent, the Incontinent and the Vicious.
Aristotle believed that every ethical virtue is an intermediate
condition between excess
and deficiency. He
set certain emotions (e.g., hate, envy, jealousy, spite, etc.) and
certain actions (e.g., adultery, theft, murder, etc.) as always
wrong, regardless of the situation or the circumstances.
In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle often focused on finding the
mean between two extremes of any particular subject;
- At times, the objections that Aristotle raises against the
arguments of his own teacher, Plato, appear to rely on faulty interpretations of
those arguments.
- Although Aristotle advised, against Plato, that knowledge of
the world could only be obtained through experience, he
frequently failed to take his own advice. Aristotle conducted
projects of careful empirical investigation, but often drifted into
abstract logical
reasoning, with the result that his work was littered with
conclusions that were not supported by empirical evidence: for
example, his assertion that objects of different mass fall at different speeds
under gravity, which
was later refuted by John Philoponus (credit is often given to Galileo, even though
Philoponus lived centuries earlier).
- In the Middle
Ages, roughly from the 12th century to the 15th century, the
philosophy of Aristotle became firmly established dogma. His works were
wide-ranging and systematic so that they could give the impression that
no significant matter had been left unsettled. He was also much
less inclined to employ the skeptical methods of his predecessors, Socrates and
Plato.
- Some academics have suggested that Aristotle was unaware of
much of the current science of his own time.
Aristotle was called not a great philosopher, but "The
Philosopher" by Scholastic thinkers. It required a repudiation of some
Aristotelian principles for the sciences and the arts to free
themselves for the discovery of modern scientific laws and
empirical methods.
The loss of his works
Though we know that Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises
(Cicero described his
literary style as "a river of gold"), the originals have been lost
in time. The story of the original manuscripts of his treatises is
described by Strabo in
his Geography and Plutarch in his "Parallel Lives, Sulla": The manuscripts were left from
Aristotle to Theophrastus, from Theophrastus to Neleus of Scepsis,
from Neleus to his heirs. Their descendants sold them to Apellicon of Teos.
When Lucius
Cornelius Sulla occupied Athens in 86 BC, he carried off the
library of Appellicon to Rome, where they were first published in 60 BC from the
grammarian Tyrranion of Amisus and then by philosopher Andronicus of
Rhodes.
Bibliography
Note: Bekker
numbers are often used to uniquely identify passages of
Aristotle. Other works, such On Colours may have been products
of Aristotle's successors at the Lyceum, e.g., Theophrastus and Straton. Still others acquired
Aristotle's name through similarities in doctrine or content, such
as the De Plantis, possibly by Nicolaus of
Damascus. A final category, omitted here, includes medieval
palmistries,
astrological and
magical texts whose
connection to Aristotle is purely fanciful and
self-promotional.
Logical writings
-
Organon (collected
works on logic):
- (1a) Categories (or Categoriae)
- (16a) On
Interpretation (or De Interpretatione)
- (24a) Prior Analytics (or Analytica
Priora)
- (71a) Posterior Analytics (or Analytica
Posteriora)
- (100b) Topics (or Topica)
- (164a) On Sophistical Refutations (or De
Sophisticis Elenchis)
Physical and scientific writings
- (184a) Physics (or Physica)
- (268a) On the
Heavens (or De Caelo)
- (314a) On Generation and Corruption (or De Generatione et
Corruptione)
- (338a) Meteorology (or Meteorologica)
- (391a) On the
Cosmos (or De Mundo, or On the Universe)
*
- (402a) On the
Soul (or De Anima)
- (436a) Little Physical Treatises (or Parva
Naturalia):
- On Sense and the Sensible (or De Sensu et
Sensibilibus)
- On Memory and Reminiscence (or De Memoria et
Reminiscentia)
- On Sleep and Sleeplessness (or De Somno et
Vigilia)
- On Dreams
(or De Insomniis) *
- On Prophesying by Dreams (or De Divinatione per
Somnum)
- On Longevity and Shortness of Life (or De
Longitudine et Brevitate Vitae)
- On
Youth and Old Age (On Life and Death) (or De Juventute
et Senectute, De Vita et Morte)
- On
Breathing (or De Respiratione)
- (481a) On Breath
(or De Spiritu) *
- (486a) History of Animals (or Historia Animalium, or
On the History of Animals, or Description of
Animals)
- (639a) On the Parts of Animals (or De Partibus
Animalium)
- (698a) On the Gait of Animals (or De Motu Animalium,
or On the Movement of Animals)
- (704a) On the Progression of Animals (or De Incessu
Animalium)
- (715a) On the Generation of Animals (or De Generatione
Animalium)
- (791a) On
Colours (or De Coloribus) *
- (800a) De
audibilibus
- (805a) Physiognomics (or Physiognomonica) *
- On Plants (or
De Plantis) *
- (830a) On Marvellous Things Heard (or Mirabilibus
Auscultationibus, or On Things Heard) *
- (847a) Mechanical Problems (or Mechanica) *
- (859a) Problems (or Problemata) *
- (968a) On
Indivisible Lines (or De Lineis Insecabilibus)
*
- (973a) Situations and Names of Winds (or Ventorum
Situs) *
- (974a) On
Melissus, Xenophanes and Gorgias (or MXG) * The
section On Xenophanes starts at 977a13, the section On Gorgias
starts at 979a11.
Metaphysical writings
- (980a) Metaphysics (or Metaphysica)
Ethical writings
- (1094a) Nicomachean Ethics (or Ethica Nicomachea, or
The Ethics)
- (1181a) Great
Ethics (or Magna Moralia) *
- (1214a) Eudemian Ethics (or Ethica Eudemia)
- (1249a) Virtues and Vices (or De Virtutibus et Vitiis
Libellus, Libellus de virtutibus) *
- (1252a) Politics (or Politica)
- (1343a) Economics (or Oeconomica)
Aesthetic writings
- (1354a) Rhetoric (or Ars Rhetorica, or The Art of
Rhetoric or Treatise on Rhetoric)
- Rhetoric
to Alexander (or Rhetorica ad Alexandrum) *
- (1447a) Poetics
(or Ars Poetica)
A work outside the Corpus Aristotelicum
- The Constitution of the Athenians (or Athenaion
Politeia, or The Athenian Constitution)
Specific editions
- Princeton
University Press: The Complete Works of Aristotle: The
Revised Oxford Translation (2 Volume Set; 2), edited by
Jonathan
Barnes ISBN 0-691-09950-2 (The most complete recent
translation of Aristotle's extant works)
- Oxford
University Press: Clarendon Aristotle Series. Scholarly
edition
- Harvard
University Press: Loeb
Classical Library (hardbound; publishes in Greek, with
English translations on facing pages)
- Oxford
Classical Texts (hardbound; Greek only)
Named after Aristotle
- Aristoteles, a crater on the Moon.
- The Aristotle University of Thessaloniki
- Aristotelous Square
Notes
link does not work
Further reading
The secondary literature on Aristotle is vast. Indianapolis:
Hackett.
- An classic overview by one of Aristotle's most prominent
English translators, in print since 1923.
- Scaltsas, T.
This web site and associated pages are not associated with, endorsed by, or sponsored by The Aristotle Corporation and has no official or unofficial affiliation with The Aristotle Corporation.